I have another post over at Ordinary Times! Click here to read it and comment.
Sunday, January 18, 2015
Saturday, January 17, 2015
First question, am I a bread thief?
(I've just posted a slightly edited version of this at the OT as a guest poster. Click here to read it and the comments.)
When is it wrong to steal and when is it okay?
If you believe that all property is theft, then it's not much of a
stretch to believe it's never wrong to steal, unless you're talking about
someone who owns property, in which case it's wrong for that person to steal. If on
the other hand you believe that private property is the eleventh commandment
handed down from Mt.
Sinai, then it's not much
of a stretch to say it's always wrong to steal.
Few of us (I suspect) swing in that way, and of those who do, most (I suspect)
at least allow for attenuating circumstances.
We'd say that sometimes, it's okay to steal. Or it's never okay to steal, but sometimes
it's at least understandable why someone might, and in some cases the thief and
not the rightful owner of what is stolen is the more sympathetic party. (I leave aside here the question of how one's
ownership becomes "rightful" in the first place, although the less
absolutist among us might very well address that question.)
Take the poor, starving bread thief, who steals a loaf from
SuperMegaWalCorporation to feed his family.
To honor the spirit of this example, we should suppose that the thief
has no other way to get bread or comparable aliment, that the family is truly
starving, and that SuperMegaWalCorporation will not be noticeably harmed by the
missing food item. (If you want, we can
stipulate that the bread is about to expire and SuperMegaWalCorporation would
have to write it off as a loss anyway.)
I suspect most of us would probably say it's not wrong for that person to
steal that item in that circumstance. Or
if we concede the theft to be wrong, most of us would hesitate before throwing
the full condemnation of law and morality against him.
How often do those circumstances actually happen? I don't know.
I suppose they occur more often in the developing countries than in the
first world. Not having lived in poverty
myself, for all I know the occurrence is much more widespread in the first
world than I think. But with due regard
to what I do not know or have not experienced, I suspect that such
circumstances tend not to occur in such a sheer, unrelenting form, where the
thief is so destitute, the stolen item so needed by people so easy to
sympathize with, and the "victim" of the theft so unharmed.
For most intents and purposes, the bread thief situation is pretty close
to a pure form or pure ideal, which real life situations may approximate but
probably rarely resemble exactly. The
destitute person may have made at least some mistakes or decisions that put him
and his family in their predicament or worsened their predicament. (Maybe a month ago he bought a king-sized
Hershey's chocolate bar and now could have spent the money on a loaf of bread.) The item stolen might be money, with which
bread could be bought, it is true, but other less necessary things can also be
bought. The thief might not even have a
family to support. Maybe the stolen
bread comes from the local bakery struggling to make ends meet and not from
SuperMegaWalCorporation. Or maybe the
"assets protection" employee at SuperMegaWalCorporation is a minimum
wage worker trying to support her own family and may have recently been warned
that one more shoplifting incident, no matter how trivial, will result in her
being written up.
I'm not saying any of this to trivialize hardship. Again, I have never known poverty. And I actually have a lot of sympathy for the
person who, for example, makes some very poor choices and is now suffering
hardship and who feels that best option at one point might very well be
shoplifting. I have less sympathy for
the SuperMegaWalCorporation. (But not no sympathy. There's a margin. Real people—employees, customers, and perhaps
elderly retirees who grew up in the Depression, fought World War II, and hold
all their savings in a 401(k) plan heavily invested in
SuperMegaWalCorproation's stock—are adversely affected, or would be if enough
such thefts occur.)
Rather, by calling the bread thief example a "pure form," what
I mean is that it's one end of a spectrum.
The closer one is to the "bread thief" condition, the more
justifiable—or at least understandable and sympathetic—the theft. The closer one is to Bernie Madoff's
condition ca. 2005, the less justifiable the theft.
But most of us aren't (I suspect) in the bread thief's
position and most of us aren't (I'm fairly confident) in Mr. Madoff's position
ca. 2005. We're (probably, or at least
sometimes) somewhere in between. Someone
with my affluence, advantages, and privilege would be wrong to shoplift from
SuperMegaWalCorporation (assuming that we're not talking about the rightness of
sticking it to corporate America). Someone who is poorer might be more
justified, or at least less wrong, to do so.
I'm not pleading for a way to judge others. If I were, I'd probably say the most
charitable thing to do is to believe from the outset that the thief in
question, even Mr. Madoff, probably on some level believes or has convinced
himself that he really is a bread thief.
But like most
injunctions against judging others, it's so hard to do in real life. For one thing, it's easy for me to plead
understanding for Mr. Madoff when I haven't been victimized by his scams
scams. For another thing, one paradox of
the New Testament's "motes and beams" admonition is that once you
invoke it against someone else, you're no longer honoring it.
Instead, I'm pleading for self-reflection. If I took a survey of the OT's readers, I
imagine that at least a majority would say that stealing is generally wrong, or
at least wrong in some circumstances, but acceptable (or mitigated) in other
circumstances. Same thing with
lying. Same thing with killing.
But how confident are we—how confident am I—that we are more
like the bread thief and less like Mr. Madoff?
Is that music video I watch on YouTube for free an instance of me
getting something I really need, or is it me stealing from the artist and
production crews? Does my suspicion that
Mr. Obama's "if you like your
insurance you can keep it" lie was necessary to pass the ACA justify the dishonesty as long as poorer
people get better coverage? (For the
record, I do watch/listen to YouTube music videos without any concern for
whether the video is sponsored by the artist.
And I
do temporize Mr. Obama's lie because of the end it (probably) helped
effect.)
Here's my takeaway. Whenever you
are tempted to do something that you otherwise believe is wrong, I suggest you
ask yourself, "Am I a bread thief."
If you can't honestly say "yes," then maybe you shouldn't do
it.
To be clear, my admonition is more like a suspensatory veto
than a red light. If you're not a bread thief, then maybe you shouldn't do what you're contemplating But maybe, pending further
investigation, there may be other reasons to do it.. I don't have a firm
opinion whether or when my admonition falls in line with the ethicist's holy
trinity of duty, virtue, and utility. But
I think it works as a good first step, a practical question we should ask
before action.
Ain't no fortunate son
(This is a reprint of a guest post I submitted to the Ordinary Times blog a while back. I have edited it, mostly for clarity, but if you want to read the original and the comments (which are now closed), please click here. Tod Kelly at the league came up with the title, which I think is a good one.)
Joseph Epstein has written a defense of the military draft at The Atlantic online. In that article, he rehashed the points generally raised in favor of the draft. But those points are not as strong as he thinks they are and they fail to address some critical objections to the draft.
We are probably all familiar with the arguments Epstein uses to argue for the draft. He says the draft would make policymakers more careful about committing soldiers abroad. He suggests that a truly universal draft would foster a sense of shared sacrifice among Americans, improve the military, and function as a social mixer, bringing together rich and poor, educated and uneducated, Gentile and Jew (and atheist?),* black and white, and so forth.
The “truly universal” in my previous sentence does a lot of work, and Epstein doesn’t utter the phrase. But it is the necessary component of what he advocates (“[a] truly American military, inclusive of all social classes….”). He presumably would not have approved of the “substitute” system of the Civil War, through which a draftee of means could hire a “substitute” in order to avoid service. He is critical of deferments during the Vietnam era, stating they made Vietnam “the first of our wars to be fought almost exclusively by an American underclass and, in part because of this, at no time did it have anything like the full support of the American people.”
His arguments don’t convince me. Let’s take what I believe to be his strongest point, namely, the egalitarian potential of compelling people from different backgrounds to work with each other. I can’t dismiss that point altogether. My only ready anecdatum runs in support of what Epstein says. The father of a friend of mine was drafted to serve in Vietnam. He says he entered the military a conservative racist and came out a pro-civil rights liberal. (I’m paraphrasing my friend’s own paraphrasing of what his father said. Take the dose of salt you deem appropriate.) I can’t deny that a “truly universal” draft might very well foster a sense of mutual understanding via interaction. And my own leveling instinct takes a certain pleasure in seeing some people (other people, not me, of course!) being knocked down a few pegs and compelled to work with their supposed inferiors.
But still, I’m skeptical. If one person becomes more broad-minded by working with a diverse group of people, I can imagine another type of person for whom familiarity fosters a hyper-tribalism of the sort that says, “I’ve worked with those people and believe you me, you don’t want to know them.” Okay, there will always be incorrigibles among us and maybe most people—maybe even most incorrigibles—really do soften their own bigotries by working with others.
I’m also skeptical because a “truly universal” draft is a fantasy, even when there is little likelihood of escaping service altogether. If it’s not hiring substitutes or winning deferments, it can be having connections to get you into the National Coast Guard Reserve, it can be having the social capital, intelligence, or skills to get the type of job that keeps you more out of danger. What about conscientious objector status? Well, if we are to have a draft, I’d want there to be C.O. provisions, and I’d want access to those provisions to be expansive ones. But then the draft is not truly universal (and C.O. status, as I understand, is hard to secure anyway, and someone with legal representation—read: social capital and real capital, or being born into a religious tradition that disavows violence—would have a much better shot at it).
But as I said, that was Epstein’s strongest point and I can’t dismiss it altogether. It reminds me of a very thoughtful comment ScarletNumbers made a while back in response to one of my posts on neoliberalism: “I would still rather have a Fortunate Son serve in an ‘easy’ position in the military as a draftee, rather not be in the military at all” (asterisk omitted). Even in an unfair system, some service for all is fairer than some people getting off free. And ScarletNumbers might have also added that in modern warfare, the “‘easy’ position” is not always safe or easy. (My uncle was “only” a mechanic in the military in World War II, and he had very disturbing memories of what he saw and underwent, especially during the Battle of the Bulge.) And at any rate, because non-combat positions outnumber actual “combat” positions, there is a strong likelihood that any given draftee would have the supposedly “easy” position.
But that last point—non-combat positions outnumbering actual combat positions—feeds into my critique of what I take to be Epstein’s weaker point, the notion that a truly universal draft would convince our policymakers to be more careful before committing soldiers to action. Because non-combat positions, which are supposedly “safer,” outnumber combat positions and because (I suspect) “only” a small percentage of people in actual combat positions suffer debilitating physical wounds, a policymaker might very well believe the odds are pretty good in favor his or her loved ones in the military, coming out okay.
I suppose that because we’ve never had a truly universal draft, I don’t really have a basis of comparison for Eptstein’s claim that policymakers would be more careful with their use of the military. But I will point out that Truman committed US soldiers to Korea pretty quickly even though there was a draft. The Gulf of Tonkin Resolution, which occurred during a time when the draft was in force and which empowered President Johnson to wage the Vietnam War, passed the Senate with only two dissents, fewer dissents than the authorization to invade Iraq in 1991 and 2002.
And then there’s World War II. I admit, it lends support to Epstein’s point. That is so not only because of the sense of shared sacrifice Americans supposedly felt during the war, but also because before Pearl Harbor there was fairly strong, albeit eroding, opposition to entering the conflict, and FDR had a hard time convincing the US to go to war. Maybe what opposition there was to entry owed something to the fact that the draft had already been implemented in 1940? Even so, the “Good War” was, I hope, exceptional, as noted by the tendency to call it “good,” as if wars by definition are presumptively bad. If a similar conflict arises, or if, as in a hypothetical commenter Roger once offered, the Mongols are surrounding the city gates, I’ll be prepared to reopen the debate, at least as it applies to that conflict.**
But that debate will have to account for one objection that Epstein—who says that “[a]rguments against the draft…are mostly technical”—declines to address. Compulsory military service meets my common-sense definition (but apparently, not the Supreme Court’s definition) of “involuntary servitude.” It requires a person to put his life on hold for a time—I believe the standard term of service was two years during the Cold War Era draft—and while in service, that person can be ordered to put his life in danger. And I believe involuntary servitude is wrong, unless it is the punishment for a crime for which someone has been duly convicted. And even without the Thirteenth Amendment, I’d still believe it would be wrong.
True, the draft is not chattel slavery. But it is compulsory service, and if someone who would otherwise not choose to serve is compelled to serve or to face harsh consequences for not serving, then his service is involuntary.
The chief argument against my “involuntary servitude” point is to draw an analogy to jury duty or to the United States’ history of militia service. And while I don’t fully sign on to Vikram Bath’s argument against analogies, I’ll point out the differences between military conscription and jury and militia service. For most people called to jury duty, the process lasts only one day unless they are empanelled. For most people who are empanelled, the duty lasts only about a week. For only a small number, the duty may last months. And only in very rare, Grisham-style, circumstances is a juror’s life ever in danger. (Am I wrong? I admit I don’t have a cite, but I do ask for the proof.)
Militia duty, when it’s not just an opportunity for homosocial male conviviality, is regular training for the possibility that the local community, or perhaps the country, might be invaded or imminently threatened in some way. I’m not in principle opposed to militia duty defined that way. But even then, I’d want the threat to be imminent. And if the Mongols*** truly are at the city’s gates, I’d want to be sure that a tribute to pay them to go away is not a possibility before I’d admit to the state’s authority to compel my or anyone else’s service.
Whether in the moment I’d have the courage of my convictions to refuse to serve—or more likely, given my less-than-draftable age of 41, to help others refuse to serve—is another issue.
—————–
*Yes, I’m aware that Jewishness is as much an ethnicity as it is a creed, but Epstein’s example—a sergeant berating his Christian soldiers to go to Church and his “Hebrew” soldiers to honor the Sabbath—focuses on the creedal aspect of Jewishness.
**For the record, I believe Roger was arguing against compulsory service, stating that his hypothetical situation rarely arises.
***It probably needs to be said that I mean no offense to Mongolians or people with Mongolian roots. I also realize the “Mongol horde” was not what European and Chinese myth has made it out to be and according to one interpretation, seems to have fit in a pattern of China’s relationship with its neighbors to its North. See Thomas J. Barfield’s The Perilous Frontier: Nomadic Empires and China, 221 B.C. to A.D. 1757. (1989)
Joseph Epstein has written a defense of the military draft at The Atlantic online. In that article, he rehashed the points generally raised in favor of the draft. But those points are not as strong as he thinks they are and they fail to address some critical objections to the draft.
We are probably all familiar with the arguments Epstein uses to argue for the draft. He says the draft would make policymakers more careful about committing soldiers abroad. He suggests that a truly universal draft would foster a sense of shared sacrifice among Americans, improve the military, and function as a social mixer, bringing together rich and poor, educated and uneducated, Gentile and Jew (and atheist?),* black and white, and so forth.
The “truly universal” in my previous sentence does a lot of work, and Epstein doesn’t utter the phrase. But it is the necessary component of what he advocates (“[a] truly American military, inclusive of all social classes….”). He presumably would not have approved of the “substitute” system of the Civil War, through which a draftee of means could hire a “substitute” in order to avoid service. He is critical of deferments during the Vietnam era, stating they made Vietnam “the first of our wars to be fought almost exclusively by an American underclass and, in part because of this, at no time did it have anything like the full support of the American people.”
His arguments don’t convince me. Let’s take what I believe to be his strongest point, namely, the egalitarian potential of compelling people from different backgrounds to work with each other. I can’t dismiss that point altogether. My only ready anecdatum runs in support of what Epstein says. The father of a friend of mine was drafted to serve in Vietnam. He says he entered the military a conservative racist and came out a pro-civil rights liberal. (I’m paraphrasing my friend’s own paraphrasing of what his father said. Take the dose of salt you deem appropriate.) I can’t deny that a “truly universal” draft might very well foster a sense of mutual understanding via interaction. And my own leveling instinct takes a certain pleasure in seeing some people (other people, not me, of course!) being knocked down a few pegs and compelled to work with their supposed inferiors.
But still, I’m skeptical. If one person becomes more broad-minded by working with a diverse group of people, I can imagine another type of person for whom familiarity fosters a hyper-tribalism of the sort that says, “I’ve worked with those people and believe you me, you don’t want to know them.” Okay, there will always be incorrigibles among us and maybe most people—maybe even most incorrigibles—really do soften their own bigotries by working with others.
I’m also skeptical because a “truly universal” draft is a fantasy, even when there is little likelihood of escaping service altogether. If it’s not hiring substitutes or winning deferments, it can be having connections to get you into the National Coast Guard Reserve, it can be having the social capital, intelligence, or skills to get the type of job that keeps you more out of danger. What about conscientious objector status? Well, if we are to have a draft, I’d want there to be C.O. provisions, and I’d want access to those provisions to be expansive ones. But then the draft is not truly universal (and C.O. status, as I understand, is hard to secure anyway, and someone with legal representation—read: social capital and real capital, or being born into a religious tradition that disavows violence—would have a much better shot at it).
But as I said, that was Epstein’s strongest point and I can’t dismiss it altogether. It reminds me of a very thoughtful comment ScarletNumbers made a while back in response to one of my posts on neoliberalism: “I would still rather have a Fortunate Son serve in an ‘easy’ position in the military as a draftee, rather not be in the military at all” (asterisk omitted). Even in an unfair system, some service for all is fairer than some people getting off free. And ScarletNumbers might have also added that in modern warfare, the “‘easy’ position” is not always safe or easy. (My uncle was “only” a mechanic in the military in World War II, and he had very disturbing memories of what he saw and underwent, especially during the Battle of the Bulge.) And at any rate, because non-combat positions outnumber actual “combat” positions, there is a strong likelihood that any given draftee would have the supposedly “easy” position.
But that last point—non-combat positions outnumbering actual combat positions—feeds into my critique of what I take to be Epstein’s weaker point, the notion that a truly universal draft would convince our policymakers to be more careful before committing soldiers to action. Because non-combat positions, which are supposedly “safer,” outnumber combat positions and because (I suspect) “only” a small percentage of people in actual combat positions suffer debilitating physical wounds, a policymaker might very well believe the odds are pretty good in favor his or her loved ones in the military, coming out okay.
I suppose that because we’ve never had a truly universal draft, I don’t really have a basis of comparison for Eptstein’s claim that policymakers would be more careful with their use of the military. But I will point out that Truman committed US soldiers to Korea pretty quickly even though there was a draft. The Gulf of Tonkin Resolution, which occurred during a time when the draft was in force and which empowered President Johnson to wage the Vietnam War, passed the Senate with only two dissents, fewer dissents than the authorization to invade Iraq in 1991 and 2002.
And then there’s World War II. I admit, it lends support to Epstein’s point. That is so not only because of the sense of shared sacrifice Americans supposedly felt during the war, but also because before Pearl Harbor there was fairly strong, albeit eroding, opposition to entering the conflict, and FDR had a hard time convincing the US to go to war. Maybe what opposition there was to entry owed something to the fact that the draft had already been implemented in 1940? Even so, the “Good War” was, I hope, exceptional, as noted by the tendency to call it “good,” as if wars by definition are presumptively bad. If a similar conflict arises, or if, as in a hypothetical commenter Roger once offered, the Mongols are surrounding the city gates, I’ll be prepared to reopen the debate, at least as it applies to that conflict.**
But that debate will have to account for one objection that Epstein—who says that “[a]rguments against the draft…are mostly technical”—declines to address. Compulsory military service meets my common-sense definition (but apparently, not the Supreme Court’s definition) of “involuntary servitude.” It requires a person to put his life on hold for a time—I believe the standard term of service was two years during the Cold War Era draft—and while in service, that person can be ordered to put his life in danger. And I believe involuntary servitude is wrong, unless it is the punishment for a crime for which someone has been duly convicted. And even without the Thirteenth Amendment, I’d still believe it would be wrong.
True, the draft is not chattel slavery. But it is compulsory service, and if someone who would otherwise not choose to serve is compelled to serve or to face harsh consequences for not serving, then his service is involuntary.
The chief argument against my “involuntary servitude” point is to draw an analogy to jury duty or to the United States’ history of militia service. And while I don’t fully sign on to Vikram Bath’s argument against analogies, I’ll point out the differences between military conscription and jury and militia service. For most people called to jury duty, the process lasts only one day unless they are empanelled. For most people who are empanelled, the duty lasts only about a week. For only a small number, the duty may last months. And only in very rare, Grisham-style, circumstances is a juror’s life ever in danger. (Am I wrong? I admit I don’t have a cite, but I do ask for the proof.)
Militia duty, when it’s not just an opportunity for homosocial male conviviality, is regular training for the possibility that the local community, or perhaps the country, might be invaded or imminently threatened in some way. I’m not in principle opposed to militia duty defined that way. But even then, I’d want the threat to be imminent. And if the Mongols*** truly are at the city’s gates, I’d want to be sure that a tribute to pay them to go away is not a possibility before I’d admit to the state’s authority to compel my or anyone else’s service.
Whether in the moment I’d have the courage of my convictions to refuse to serve—or more likely, given my less-than-draftable age of 41, to help others refuse to serve—is another issue.
—————–
*Yes, I’m aware that Jewishness is as much an ethnicity as it is a creed, but Epstein’s example—a sergeant berating his Christian soldiers to go to Church and his “Hebrew” soldiers to honor the Sabbath—focuses on the creedal aspect of Jewishness.
**For the record, I believe Roger was arguing against compulsory service, stating that his hypothetical situation rarely arises.
***It probably needs to be said that I mean no offense to Mongolians or people with Mongolian roots. I also realize the “Mongol horde” was not what European and Chinese myth has made it out to be and according to one interpretation, seems to have fit in a pattern of China’s relationship with its neighbors to its North. See Thomas J. Barfield’s The Perilous Frontier: Nomadic Empires and China, 221 B.C. to A.D. 1757. (1989)
Friday, January 2, 2015
That myth might not be the myth you think you're busting
I've written a post on "myth busting" over at the Ordinary Times. Click here if you'd like to read it.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)